Context
Plato (427–347 B.C.E.) is notorious
for attacking art in Book 10 of his Republic .
According to Plato's Theory of Forms, objects in this world are imitations or
approximations of ideal Forms that are the true reality. A chair in this world
is just an imitation or instantiation of the Form of Chair. That being the
case, art is twice removed from reality, as it is just an imitation of an
imitation: a painting of a chair is an imitation of a chair which is in turn an
imitation of the Form of Chair. Further, Plato argues that art serves to excite
the emotions, which can detract from the balanced reasoning that is essential
to virtue.
Aristotle's Poetics can be read as a response to Plato's
attack on art. Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.) was a student at Plato's Academy from
the time he was seventeen until Plato's death some twenty years later. He spent
the next twelve years engaging in scientific research and serving as tutor to
the then teenaged Alexander the Great. He returned to Athens in 335 B.C.E., and
founded his own school on the steps of the Lyceum. He remained there until 323
B.C.E., when he was forced to leave as a result of his associations with
Alexander. He died a year later of natural causes. The Lyceum remained open
until 525 C.E., when it was closed by the emperor Justinian.
None of the works of Aristotle that
we have today were actually published by Aristotle. He wrote a number of
treatises and dialogues, but these have all been lost. What survives are
collections of notes, possibly from lecture courses Aristotle gave at the
Lyceum, which are often unclear or incomplete. The Poetics, in true form, was likely a much longer
work than the one we have today. Aristotle supposedly wrote a second book on
comedy, which is now lost.
The main focus of the Poetics is on Greek tragedy. Though there were
thousands of tragedies and scores of playwrights, we only have thirty-three
extant tragedies, written by the three great tragedians: Aeschylus (525–456 B.C.E.), Sophocles (496–405
B.C.E.), and Euripides (485–406 B.C.E.). Tragedies were
performed in Athens twice annually at festivals in honor of Dionysus, the god
of wine and excess. Though the tragedies likely evolved out of religious
ceremonies celebrating the cycle of the seasons, they became increasingly
secular. The dramatic festivals were immensely important events, and the
winning playwrights achieved great fame.
The Poetics also discusses epic poetry, using the
example of Homer (eighth century B.C.E.) almost exclusively. Homer wrote two
great epics, the Iliad and
the Odyssey , which deal with the fall of Troy
and Odysseus's subsequent wanderings respectively. These epics are the source
of a great number of Greek tragedies and are considered among the earliest
great works of world literature.
Though the Poetics is not one of Aristotle's major works,
it has exercised a great deal of influence on subsequent literary theory,
particularly in the Renaissance. Later interpreters unfortunately turned many
of Aristotle's suggestions into strict laws, restricting the flexibility of
drama in ways that Aristotle would not have anticipated. The tragedies of
Racine and Corneille in particular are formed according to these demands. Even
though such great playwrights as Shakespeare often went against these laws,
they were held as the model for writing tragedy well into the nineteenth
century.
Important Terms
Mimesis - Mimesis is the act of creating in someone's
mind, through artistic representation, an idea or ideas that the person will
associate with past experience. Roughly translatable as "imitation," mimesis in poetry is the act of telling
stories that are set in the real world. The events in the story need not have
taken place, but the telling of the story will help the listener or viewer to
imagine the events taking place in the real world.
Hamartia - This word translates
almost directly as "error," though it is often rendered more
elaborately as "tragic flaw." Tragedy, according to Aristotle,
involves the downfall of a hero, and this downfall is effected by some error on
the part of the hero. This error need not be an overarching moral failing: it
could be a simple matter of not knowing something or forgetting something.
Anagnorisis - This word translates
as "recognition" or "discovery." In tragedy, it describes
the moment where the hero, or some other character, passes from ignorance to
knowledge. This could be a recognition of a long lost friend or family member,
or it could be a sudden recognition of some fact about oneself, as is the case with
Oedipus. Anagnorisis often occurs at the climax of a
tragedy in tandem with peripeteia.
Mythos - When dealing with
tragedy, this word is usually translated as "plot," but unlike
"plot," mythos can be applied to all works of art.
Not so much a matter of what happens and in what order, mythos deals with how the elements of a
tragedy (or a painting, sculpture, etc.) come together to form a coherent and
unified whole. The overall message or impression that we come away with is what
is conveyed to us by the mythos of a piece.
Katharsis - This word was
normally used in ancient Greece by doctors to mean "purgation" or by
priests to mean "purification." In the context of tragedy, Aristotle
uses it to talk about a purgation or purification of emotions. Presumably, this
means that katharsis is a release of built up emotional
energy, much like a good cry. After katharsis, we reach a more stable and neutral
emotional state.
Peripeteia - A reversal, either
from good to bad or bad to good. Peripeteia
often occurs at the climax of a story, often prompted by anagnorisis. Indeed, we might
say that the peripeteia is the climax of a story: it is the
turning point in the action, where things begin to move toward a conclusion.
Lusis - Literally
"untying," the lusis is all the action in a tragedy from
the climax onward. All the plot threads that have been woven together in thedesis are slowly unraveled until we reach
the conclusion of the play.
Desis - Literally
"tying," the desis is all the action in a tragedy leading
up to the climax. Plot threads are craftily woven together to form a more and
more complex mess. At the peripeteia,
or turning point, these plot threads begin to unravel in what is called the lusis, or denouement.
Analytical
Overview
Aristotle approaches poetry with the same scientific
method with which he treats physics and biology. He begins by collecting and
categorizing all the data available to him and then he draws certain
conclusions and advances certain theses in accordance with his analysis. In the
case of tragedy, this means he divides it into six parts, identifies plot as
the most important part, and examines the different elements of plot and
character that seem to characterize successful tragedies. He tentatively
suggests that tragedy ultimately aims at the arousal of pity and fear and at
the katharsis of these
emotions. Then he begins to lay out certain theories as to what makes a good
tragedy: it must focus on a certain type of hero who must follow a certain
trajectory within a plot that is tightly unified, etc. Aristotle's conclusions,
then, are based less on personal taste and more on an observation of what tends
to produce the most powerful effects.
Aristotle's method raises the fundamental question of
whether poetry can be studied in the same way as the natural sciences. Though
there are some benefits to Aristotle's method, the ultimate answer seems to be
"no." The scientific method relies on the assumption that there are
certain regularities or laws that govern the behavior of the phenomena being
investigated. This method has been particularly successful in the physical
sciences: Isaac
Newton, for example, managed to reduce all mechanical behavior to
three simple laws. However, art does not seem to be governed by unchanging,
unquestionable laws in the same way that nature is. Art often thrives and
progresses by questioning the assumptions or laws that a previous generation
has accepted. While Aristotle insisted on the primacy and unity of plot, Samuel
Beckett has achieved
fame as one of this century's greatest playwrights by constructing plays that
arguably have no plot at all. Closer to Aristotle's time, Euripides often violated the Aristotelian
principles of structure and balance in a conscious effort to depict a universe
that is neither structured nor balanced. Not surprisingly, Aristotle seems to
have preferred Sophocles to Euripides.
These remarks on Sophocles and Euripides bring us to
another problem of interpreting Aristotle: we have a very limited stock of
Greek tragedies against which to test Aristotle's theories. Aristotle could
have been familiar with hundreds, or even thousands, of tragedies. All we have
today are thirty-three plays by three tragedians. As a result, it is difficult
to say to what extent most tragedies fit Aristotle's observations. Those that
we have, however, often grossly violate Aristotle's requirement. The best
example we have of an Aristotelian tragedy is Oedipus Rex, so it is no wonder that Aristotle makes
such frequent reference to it in his examples.
Three points stand out as probably the most important
in the Poetics: (1) the
interpretation of poetry as mimesis,
(2) the insistence on the primacy and unity of mythos, or plot, and (3)
the view that tragedy serves to arouse the emotions of pity and fear and then
to effect a katharsis of these emotions. (1) is discussed in
the commentary on Chapters 1–3, (2)is discussed in the commentary on Chapter 6
and Chapters 7–9, and (3) is discussed in the commentary on Chapter 6 as well.
Chapters 1–3
Summary
Aristotle proposes to approach
poetry from a scientific viewpoint, examining the constituent parts of poetry
and drawing conclusions from those observations. First, he lists the different
kinds of poetry: epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, dithyrambic poetry, and most
flute-playing and lyre-playing. Next, he remarks that all of these kinds of
poetry are mimetic, or imitative, but that there are significant differences
between them.
The first kind of distinction is the
means they employ. Just as a painter employs paint and a sculptor employs
stone, the poet employs language, rhythm, and harmony, either singly or in combinations.
For instance, flute-playing and lyre-playing employ rhythm and harmony, while
dance employs only rhythm. He also addresses the question of non-poetic
language, arguing that poetry is essentially mimetic, whether it is in verse or
in prose. Thus, Homer is a poet, while Empedocles, a philosopher who wrote in
verse, is not. While Empedocles writes in verse, his writing is not mimetic,
and so it is not poetry. In tragedy, comedy, and other kinds of poetry, rhythm,
language, and harmony are all used. In some cases, as in lyric poetry, all
three are used together, while in other cases, as in comedy or tragedy, the
different parts come in to play at different times.
The second distinction is the
objects that are imitated. All poetry represents actions with agents who are
either better than us, worse than us, or quite like us. For instance, tragedy
and epic poetry deal with characters who are better than us, while comedy and
parody deal with characters who are worse than us.
The final distinction is with the
manner of representation: the poet either speaks directly in narrative or
assumes the characters of people in the narrative and speaks through them. For
instance, many poets tell straight narratives while Homer alternates between
narrative and accounts of speeches given by characters in his narrative. In
tragedy and comedy, the poet speaks exclusively through assumed characters.
Analysis
The very first paragraph of the Poetics gives us a hint as to how we should
approach the work: it is meant to be descriptive rather than prescriptive. That
is, Aristotle is not so much interested in arguing that poetry or tragedy should be one thing or another. Rather, he
wants to look at past examples of poetry—tragedy in particular—and by
dissecting them and examining their constituent parts to arrive at some general
sense of what poetry is and how it works.
This is the same scientific method
that Aristotle employs so successfully in examining natural phenomena: careful
observation followed by tentative theories to explain the observations. The
immediate and pressing question, then, is whether Aristotle is right in
applying his scientific method to poetry. Physical phenomena are subject to
unchanging, natural laws, and presumably a careful study of the phenomena matched
with a little insight might uncover what these natural laws are. Aristotle
seems to be proceeding with the assumption that the same is true for poetry:
its growth and development has been guided by unchanging, natural laws, and the
Poetics seeks to uncover
these laws.
The results are mixed. In some
cases, what Aristotle says seems quite right, while in others his conclusions
seem very limiting. We will examine this question further when Aristotle delves
deeper into the elements of tragedy.
Before going any further, we might
do well to clarify some terms. When Aristotle talks about "art" or
"poetry" he is not talking about what we might understand by these
words. "Art" is the translation of the Greek word techne and is closely related
to "artifice" and "artificial." Art for Aristotle is
anything that is made by human beings as opposed to being found in nature.
Thus, poetry, painting, and sculpture count as "art," but so do
chairs, horseshoes, and sandals.
Our conception of "art" is
more closely (but not exactly) approximated by what Aristotle calls
"mimetic art." The Greek word mimesis defies exact translation, though
"imitation" works quite well in the context of the Poetics. A chair is something
you can sit in, but a painting of a chair is merely an imitation, or
representation, of a real chair.
Paintings use paint to imitate real
life, and sculptures use stone. Poetry is distinguished as the mimetic art that
uses language, rhythm, and harmony to imitate real life, language obviously
being the most crucial component.
This raises the question of in what
way poetry imitates, or "mimics," real life. The events in Oedipus Rex did not actually happen in real life.
In fact, it is important that tragedy be fictional and that there be an
understanding that the events taking place on stage are not real: no one should
call the police when Hamlet kills Polonius. Still, tragedy deals with humans
who speak and act in a way that real humans conceivably could have spoken and
acted. It is important that there be an understanding that the account is
fictional, but it must also be close enough to reality that it is plausible.
There are significant differences
between the kind of poetry discussed here and our conception of poetry. In
modern times, the definition of poetry is closely linked to its being written
in verse. Aristotle directly contradicts that definition, pointing out that
Empedocles' philosophical verses are not poetry; they present ideas rather than
imitate life.
Further, narrative is essential to
Aristotle's definition of poetry. Not only comedy and tragedy, but also the
epic poetry of the Greeks tells stories, as we find in the Iliad and the Odyssey.
Both drama and epic poetry are fictional accounts that imitate real life in
some way. On the other hand, a great deal of poetry in the modern world does
not imitate life in any obvious way. For instance, the Robert Burns line,
"My love is like a red, red rose" may be said to "imitate"
or represent the poet's love for a woman, but by that token, Empedocles' verses
might be said to "imitate" or represent certain philosophical
concepts.
Aristotle is not trying to condemn
Robert Burns for writing love poems; he is simply trying to catalog the
different kinds of poetry that existed in his time. They all employ language,
rhythm, and harmony in some way or another, they all deal with people who are
engaging in certain kinds of action, and they all involve some sort of direct
or indirect narrative. Whether something is an epic poem, a comedy, or a
tragedy depends on how it fits within these categories. For instance, a tragedy
is a composite of language, rhythm, and harmony that deals with agents who are
on the whole better than us, and the poet speaks directly through these agents.
Chapters 4–5
Summary
Aristotle suggests that it is human
nature to write and appreciate poetry. We are by nature imitative creatures
that learn and excel by imitating others, and we naturally take delight in
works of imitation. As evidence of the claim that we delight in imitation, he
points out that we are fascinated by representations of dead bodies or
disgusting animals even though the things themselves would repel us. Aristotle
suggests that we can also learn by examining representations and imitations of
things and that learning is one of the greatest pleasures there is. Rhythm and
harmony also come naturally to us, so that poetry gradually evolved out of our
improvisations with these media.
As poetry evolved, a sharp division
developed between serious writers who would write about noble characters in
lofty hymns and panegyrics, and meaner writers who would write about ignoble
characters in demeaning invectives. Tragedy and comedy are later developments
that are the grandest representation of their respective traditions: tragedy of
the lofty tradition and comedy of the mean tradition.
Aristotle stops short of saying that
tragedy has achieved its complete and finished form. He lists four innovations
in the development from improvised dithyrambs toward the tragedies of his day.
Dithyrambs were sung in honor of Dionysus, god of wine, by a chorus of around
fifty men and boys, often accompanied by a narrator. Aeschylus is responsible for the first
innovation, reducing the number of the chorus and introducing a second actor on
stage, which made dialogue the central focus of the poem. Second, Sophocles
added a third actor and also introduced background scenery. Third, tragedy
developed an air of seriousness, and the meter changed from a trochaic rhythm,
which is more suitable for dancing, to an iambic rhythm, which is closer to the
natural rhythms of conversational speech. Fourth, tragedy developed a plurality
of episodes, or acts.
Next, Aristotle elaborates on what
he means when he says that comedy deals with people worse than us ourselves,
saying that comedy deals with the ridiculous. He defines the ridiculous as a
kind of ugliness that does no harm to anybody else. Aristotle is able only to
give a very sketchy account of the origins of comedy, because it was not
generally treated with the same respect as tragedy and so there are fewer
records of the innovations that led to its present form.
While both tragedy and epic poetry
deal with lofty subjects in a grand style of verse, Aristotle notes three
significant differences between the two genres. First, tragedy is told in a
dramatic, rather than narrative, form, and employs several different kinds of verse
while epic poetry employs only one. Second, the action of a tragedy is usually
confined to a single day, and so the tragedy itself is usually much shorter
than an epic poem. Third, while tragedy has all the elements that are
characteristic of epic poetry, it also has some additional elements that are
unique to it alone.
Analysis
Aristotle further elaborates on the
value of the mimetic arts with his assertion that we are naturally imitative
creatures who delight in imitation. Aristotle relates this claim to our ability
to learn and reason: we exercise our reason when seeing something as an
imitation of something else. It takes a certain level of recognition to see a
bunch of men dancing and singing in masks as imitations of characters from
ancient myths, to see stylized gestures as imitations of real action, or to see
the emotional intensity generated both by actors and audience as an imitation
of the emotional intensity that would have been felt if the action on stage
were transpiring in real life. Aristotle defines humans as rational animals,
suggesting that our rationality is what distinguishes us from other creatures.
If the ability to recognize an imitation and understand what it is meant to
represent requires reasoning, then we are delighting in that very faculty that
makes us human.
Aristotle's account of the origin of
tragedy seems on the whole quite sound. The sparseness of archaeological and
other evidence has long frustrated scholars, but it seems that Aristotle's
suggestion that tragedy evolved from the dithyramb is as good as any we have.
Dionysus is the Greek god of vegetation and wine, and the dithyrambs in honor
of him are thought to have been part of festivals celebrating the harvest and
the changing of the seasons. These songs were thus part of religious
ceremonies, and the speaker that accompanied the large chorus was probably a
priest of some sort. Though initially improvised, these dithyrambs developed a
more rigid structure, and the speaker often engaged in dialogue with the
chorus. Aeschylus is
generally credited with the innovation of adding a second actor, which
transformed choral singing into dialogue, ritual into drama. In short,
Aeschylus invented tragedy and is the first great playwright of the Western
tradition.
Near the end of Chapter 5, Aristotle
mentions that one of the differences between tragedy and epic poetry is that
the action of a tragedy usually unfolds in the space of a single day. This is
often interpreted as one of the three "unities" of tragic drama. In
fact, the three unities—unity of action (one single plot with no loose
threads), unity of time (action takes place within a single day), and unity of
place (action takes place in a single location)—were not invented by Aristotle
at all. The Italian theorist Lodovico Castelvetro formalized these unities in
1570. This formalization was inspired by the Poetics, but it is far more restrictive than
anything Aristotle says. The only unity he insists upon, as we shall see, is
the unity of action. His reference here to the unity of time seems to be a
general guideline and not one that must be followed strictly, and there is even
less evidence to suggest that Aristotle demanded unity of place. The fact is,
Aristotle's formulas were all drawn from Greek tragedy, and these tragedies
frequently violated the unities of time and place.
Chapter 6
Summary
Aristotle now narrows his focus to
examine tragedy exclusively. In order to do so, he provides a definition of
tragedy that we can break up into seven parts: (1) it involves mimesis; (2) it is serious; (3)
the action is complete and with magnitude; (4) it is made up of language with
the "pleasurable accessories" of rhythm and harmony; (5) these
"pleasurable accessories" are not used uniformly throughout, but are
introduced in separate parts of the work, so that, for instance, some bits are
spoken in verse and other bits are sung; (6) it is performed rather than
narrated; and (7) it arouses the emotions of pity and fear and accomplishes a katharsis (purification or purgation) of these
emotions.
Next, Aristotle asserts that any
tragedy can be divided into six component parts, and that every tragedy is made
up of these six parts with nothing else besides. There is (a) the spectacle,
which is the overall visual appearance of the stage and the actors. The means
of imitation (language, rhythm, and harmony) can be divided into (b) melody,
and (c) diction, which has to do with the composition of the verses. The agents
of the action can be understood in terms of (d) character and (e) thought.
Thought seems to denote the intellectual qualities of an agent while character
seems to denote the moral qualities of an agent. Finally, there is (f) the
plot, or mythos, which is
the combination of incidents and actions in the story.
Aristotle argues that, among these
six, the plot is the most important. The characters serve to advance the action
of the story, not vice versa. The ends we pursue in life, our happiness and our
misery, all take the form of action. That is, according to Aristotle, happiness
consists in a certain kind of activity rather than in a certain quality of
character. Diction and thought are also less significant than plot: a series of
well-written speeches have nothing like the force of a well-structured tragedy.
Further, Aristotle suggests, the most powerful elements in a tragedy, the peripeteia and the anagnorisis, are
elements of the plot. Lastly, Aristotle notes that forming a solid plot is far
more difficult than creating good characters or diction.
Having asserted that the plot is the
most important of the six parts of tragedy, he ranks the remainder as follows,
from most important to least: character, thought, diction, melody, and
spectacle. Character reveals the individual motivations of the characters in
the play, what they want or don't want, and how they react to certain
situations, and this is more important to Aristotle than thought, which deals
on a more universal level with reasoning and general truths. Melody and
spectacle are simply pleasurable accessories, but melody is more important to
the tragedy than spectacle: a pretty spectacle can be arranged without a play,
and usually matters of set and costume aren't the occupation of the poet
anyway.
Analysis
Aristotle's definition of tragedy at
the beginning of this chapter is supposed to summarize what he has already
said, but it is the first mention of the katharsis. The Greek word katharsis was usually used either by doctors to
talk about purgation, the flushing of contaminants out of the system, or by
priests to talk about religious purification. In either case, it seems to refer
to a therapeutic process whereby the body or mind expels contaminants and
becomes clean and healthy. Determining exactly what role katharsis is meant to play in tragedy is
somewhat more difficult.
First, we might ask what exactly katharsis is in reference to tragedy. The idea,
it seems, is that watching a tragedy arouses the emotions of pity and fear in
us and then purges these emotions. But, by virtue of mimesis, we aren't feeling real
pity or real fear. I may feel pity for Oedipus when he learns that he has
killed his father and married his mother, but this is a different kind of pity
than the pity I feel for the homeless or for those living in war zones. I know
that Oedipus is not a real person and that no one is really suffering when I
watch Oedipus suffer. As a result, I can empathize with the character of
Oedipus without feeling any kind of guilt or obligation to help him out.
Watching tragedy has a cathartic effect because I can let go of the emotional
tension built up in me as I leave the theater. I am able to experience profound
emotion without having its consequences stay with me and harden me to
subsequent emotional shocks.
Second, we might ask to what extent katharsis is the purpose of tragedy, and to what
extent it is an occasional effect of tragedy. The question of in what way art
may be good for us is a very difficult question to answer. The best art (and
this applies to Greek tragedy) is not didactic: it does not try to tell us
outright how we ought or ought not to behave. At the same time, there is
definitely a lot we can learn from a subtle appreciation of art. The value of
art, on the whole, seems to stem more from its ability to arouse emotion and
awareness on an abstract, general level, rather than to teach us particular
truths. Oedipus Rex is valuable because it engenders a
certain state of mind, not because it teaches us to avoid marrying older women
whose family histories are uncertain.
Though katharsis may be an important effect of tragedy,
it is hardly the reason for which poets write tragedies. If that were so, poets
would be little more than emotional therapists. Again, Aristotle is writing as
an observer more than as a theorist. He has observed that tragedy has a
cathartic effect on its viewers, but he is not trying to enunciate this as the
end goal of all tragedy.
The other important concept we
encounter in this chapter is that of mythos.
While "plot" is a pretty good translation of this word in reference
to tragedy, mythos can be
applied to sculpture, music, or any other art form. Themythos of a piece of art is the way it is
structured and organized in order to make a coherent statement. Thus, when
Aristotle speaks about the "plot" of a tragedy, he is not just
referring to who did what to whom, but is speaking about how the events in the
story come together to bring out deeper, general themes.
Plot, then, is central to a tragedy,
because that is where, if at all, its value lies. If character were central to
tragedy, we would be watching Oedipus
Rex in order to learn
something about Oedipus, about what makes him tick, or how he reacts in
different situations. The character of Oedipus in itself is uninteresting: why
should we care about the personality of someone who never existed? The value of
Oedipus lies in what we can learn about ourselves and our world from observing
his fate. What we learn from a tragedy—the effect it has on us—results from the
way it is structured to draw our minds toward general truths and ideas; that
is, from its mythos.
Chapters 7–9
Summary
Aristotle elaborates on what he
means when he says that the action of a tragedy is complete in itself and with
magnitude. For a plot to be a complete whole, it must have a beginning, middle,
and end. The beginning is a point that does not necessarily follow from
anything else, which naturally has consequences following from it. The end is a
point that naturally follows from preceding events but does not have any
necessary consequences following it. The middle is a point that is naturally
connected both to events before and after it.
The magnitude of a story is
important, as it is in any art. Paintings are neither infinitesimally small nor
monstrously big because they must be of such a size as to be taken in by the
eye. Similarly, a tragedy must be of a moderate length so as to be taken in by
the memory. Usually, time limits are set by the audience or other outside
factors, but Aristotle suggests that the longer the play the greater the
magnitude, provided the poet can hold the tragedy together as one coherent
statement. As a general rule of thumb, he suggests the action should be long
enough to allow the main character to pass through a number of necessary or
probable steps that take him from fortune to misfortune or vice versa.
In insisting upon the unity of plot,
Aristotle makes it clear that he does not mean that it is enough to focus the
plot on the life of one individual. Our lives consist of all sorts of
disconnected episodes, and the story of a man's life would rarely have the
completeness necessary for a unified plot. Rather, the poet must select some
series of events from a character's life—as Homer does in the Odyssey —and craft them into a coherent
whole. Any part of a story that could be added or removed without any great
effect on the rest of the story is superfluous and takes away from the unity of
the piece.
Aristotle distinguishes between
poetry and history, saying that while history deals with what has been, poetry
deals with what might be: it presents the possible as probable or necessary.
Poetry is superior to history because history always deals with particular
cases while poetry can express universal and general truths. Tragedy gives a
feeling of necessity—or at least probability—to the way certain characters
behave in certain situations and thus gives us insight into general principles
regarding fate, choice, and so on. The worst kind of plot is the episodic plot,
where there is no seeming necessity or probability whatsoever between events.
As a medium that arouses pity and
fear, tragedy is most effective when events occur unexpectedly and yet in a
logical order. The ideal is to have the audience see the final outcome of a
tragedy as the necessary consequence of all the action that preceded it, and
yet have that outcome be totally unexpected.
Analysis
Essentially, a good plot is a
complete causal chain that leads, with necessity or probability, from beginning
to end. The beginning is the first link in a chain that is itself not
necessarily caused by any events that precede it. The events that follow are
necessary or probable consequences of this un-caused beginning. Each event
follows the next until we arrive at the end, which is also a necessary or
probable consequence of all the events that have preceded it. This end does not
itself cause any further events with any kind of necessity or probability and
so concludes the causal chain.
What kinds of plot does this
definition exclude? Aristotle explicitly condemns the episodic plot, where one
event follows another without any clear connection. Obviously, no plot is
entirely episodic, though we could also say that very few plots are so tightly
organized as to tie in every moment with seeming inevitability. The plot with a
fully integrated beginning, middle, and end is an ideal to be approximated
rather than an easily attainable goal.
That the plot of a tragedy should
consist of one uninterrupted causal chain with no superfluous elements (nothing
that is not a necessary part of this chain) is the essence of what Aristotle
means when he talks about the unity of plot or action.
Again, we should be clear that the
Greek mythos is not quite the same as the English
"plot": we are not so much talking about the sum total of the events
in the story so much as the way they are held together to form a coherent
statement. If we were thinking simply in terms of the events taking place on
stage, it would be obvious that a tragedy must have a beginning, middle, and
end. In talking about a beginning, however, Aristotle is not talking about the
first things that happen on stage so much as the first link in a causal chain
that leads logically to the conclusion.
We might come to a clearer
understanding of the unity of plot if we examine Aristotle's contrast between
tragedy and history. Aristotle seems to hold the point of view that history is
one thing after another. Event follows event, and there does not always seem to
be a connection between them. This view is contestable, to say the least: the
job of the historian, to a large extent, is to uncover some sort of connection
between events. Aristotle says that history only deals with isolated,
particular events, but a good historian can read more general truths into these
events, just as a good tragedian can draw general truths out of the stories of
particular characters.
Perhaps we would do better to
understand Aristotle's distinction as being between fact and fiction. We tell
stories to help make sense of a world that at times may seem frighteningly
meaningless. There are no beginnings or ends in real life, and the stuff in
between is nowhere near as neatly organized as it is in tragedy. The role of
the tragedian is to take a certain series of events and to trace a logical
sequence between them. The tragic action then shows us that there is some
order, some necessity, in the world around us. We learn that certain kinds of
behavior, certain choices, lead to certain consequences. Tragedy draws patterns
out of a meaningless swirl of experience. The end of the tragedy gives meaning
to all that preceded it, as if to say, "these sorts of situations, these
sorts of characters, these sorts of decisions, tend to result in this kind of a
conclusion."
This causal chain need not be
evident; in fact, Aristotle suggests that it is more interesting if it isn't.
The best plots have unexpected outcomes, but this does not mean that they take
place outside the realm of causality. Rather, unexpected twists make us aware
of how poor we are at following the momentum of necessity. To take a modern
example, the surprise ending to the movie The
Usual Suspects does not make
us feel cheated, as if something illogical took place. Rather, it makes us
realize how poorly we had understood all the action that had preceded us: it
makes us think of the whole movie in a new light.
Aristotle explicitly mentions pity
and fear in reference to the logical sequencing and unexpected outcome of
tragedy. We see that our character and actions determine our fate with chilling
justice and efficiency, but that we are mostly ignorant of the causes of this
fate and can never see it coming. We don't need to suffer Oedipus's fate to
recognize our own ignorance and vulnerability in the character of Oedipus.
Where is the rest of the summary?
ReplyDelete